Dear Tejinder,

Your essay is impeccable and well grounded. There are indeed many theoretical rats to smell as things currently stand. Your conclusion that Bit is from It also follows on one condition, which if correct will be a fatal oversight to that conclusion. Bit is short for any binary choice.

Bizarre as it may initially appear, Is existence/non-existence then one of the binary choices available? If not, why not if the universe as a whole exhibits this choice? (if our cosmology is correct). Can this Bit be denied other Its, if the universe is not denied this choice? If yes, then non-existence is one bit that does not require any It to carry it. Again, what other Bit can lie below this Bit? Would it not occupy the "very, very deep bottom" as Wheeler says? If there is actually some primordial substance, can a fundamental discrete It come from another It? Would it rather not be derived from this Bit mentioned?

So when you say, "...we believe that 'it from bit' is not a real option. 'Bit' always refers to a pre-existing 'it'", I can understand because obviously, the Binary choice I mention above does not come into your reckoning, or if it did, you don't want it included in the list of available Bits. As I claim in my essay however, it is likely that it is that Bit that will make "all problems evaporate" and not the contrary.

*Mind you, a few in this community have come to agree that this Bit should not be excluded from our list of Bits, with Ian Durham introducing another view (trying to find an escape route) in that he says probability can again dog that Bit, i.e. an It can hover between existence and non-existence.

I enjoy dialectic, so pardon my barrage of questions.

Whatever, your essay is a collector's item on how to rectify deficiencies in Quantum theory.

My essay is here as well, you may take a look.

Cheerio,

Akinbo

Thank you Akinbo, for your kind appreciation, and also for your comments, which perhaps bear similarity with those by John Selye just above. I agree to the importance of the observer/existence aspect when the matter-information relationship is considered in its broadest perspective. My response would perhaps again be somewhat along the lines of the response to John's comments.

I hope to see your essay soon.

My best wishes,

Tejinder

Dear Angelo,

You wrote an excellent essay to introduce your RMP paper and more.

I don't really understand why your work contradicts the "it from bit" philosophy.

As you write in the RMP paper, QM is a theory of measurements and seems to have "nothing to say about the world as it is". So, in the range of validity of QM, the "bit from it" makes no sense. On the other hand, QM says a lot about observer participancy and the existence of objects, and finally about the "it".

Is it that you reject QM in the microrange? In that case, you would have to explain many exotic quantum properties, from non-locality to entanglement and contextuality, am I right?

Best wishes,

Michel

    Dear Michel,

    Thank you for your kind appreciation and interesting comments.

    To put in perspective the remark you quote from our RMP paper we reproduce here the entire paragraph in which that sentence appears:

    "

    Quantum mechanics, in its standard textbook formulation, refers only to the outcomes of measurements, but it has nothing to say about the world as it is, independently of any measurement or act of observation. This is a source of serious difficulties, which have been clearly elucidated, e.g., by Bell (1990): ''It would seem that the theory is exclusively concerned about 'results of measurements,' and has nothing to say about anything else. What exactly qualifies some physical systems to play the role of 'measurer'? Was the wave function of the world waiting to jump for thousands of millions of years until a single-celled living creature appeared? Or did it have to wait a little bit longer, for some better qualified system . . . with a Ph.D.?''

    "

    This is intended as a criticism of the Copenhagen interpretation. When we say quantum mechanics is a theory of measurements, and has nothing to say about the world as it is, it is intended to mean that according to the Copenhagen viewpoint, unless a measurement is made [and information acquired] no definite reality can be ascribed (i.e. `has nothing to say about the real world') to the properties of objects [because the outcomes of successive measurements are only probabilistic, and not predictable]. This is `it from bit' suggested by the Copenhagen interpretation: make a measurement, gain statistical information (bit), and deduce the properties of the `it'. The it is claimed to be ill-defined without the bit coming first.

    We are saying this is very much tied to the Copenhagen interpretation, which interpretation we find unsatisfactory, for reasons which you saw outlined in the essay. We highlight that indeed there are interpretations/modifications of QM which explain the collapse of the wave-function and the measurement problem, without invoking observer participancy. Here the it comes first [it being the particle / wave-function / matrix] and is well-defined even before the measurement is made. Measurements give information (bit) about this preexisting it; hence bit from it. This runs contrary to the Copenhagen interpretation.

    We fully accept QM in the microrarnge. The Copenhagen interpretation, as you will agree, is not a statement about the microrange, but rather about the process of measurement. All interpretations/modifications of QM are in agreement in the microrange. The differences are only in the understanding of the measurement process and of the quantum-classical transition.

    Thank you once again for your kind interest in our work,

    Best,

    Authors

    Thanks Tejinder,

    I appreciate your input - it does seem to me that the paradigm I've created does put your option (ii) in a context that makes the Cosmos fully accessible to classical, Bio-, and Neuro-Physics. I did rate your essay highly, and am looking forward to studying it again.

    I look forward to hearing from you soon on my page,

    All the best,

    John.

    Angelo, Saikat, & Tejinder,

    I am somewhat familiar with Bohm QM, less so with dynamic collapse and I will have to read on trace dynamics. I did read something a while back about how dynamic collapse runs into some difficulties.

    Bohm QM works well enough for systems with quantum observables that have a direct correspondence with classical mechanics. Bohm's QM does not work very well without a classical-quantum correspondence. BQM contrary to what is commonly said does work in a relativistic setting. You can write the Klein-Gordon equation in real and imaginary parts, just as with the Schrodinger equation. What becomes troublesome is when you try to do interacting QFT. There is no natural ladder of states from which to describe the production of massive particles. As a result there is no workable BQM form of QED.

    These approaches to QFT, which are really forms of quantum interpretations, are minority reports. I did some work on quantum chaos where I used BQM. I used it because it is close to a classical description and is convenient for working Hamiltonian chaos. The response was not good, largely because of the Bohm part. I kept trying to argue that there is nothing erroneous with the writing the wave function in polar form, separating the Schrodinger equation into real and imaginary parts and so forth. BQM is admittedly weak in some respects, but it is not wrong. I don't think BQM can replace standard QM, nor do I think it is likely the others will either. Yet they have their niche.

    Cheers LC

      Dear Lawrence,

      Thank you for your interest in our work and for reading our essay.

      We do not quite understand what you mean by your remark:

      "Bohm QM works well enough for systems with quantum observables that have a direct correspondence with classical mechanics. Bohm's QM does not work very well without a classical-quantum correspondence."

      What we have said in our essay is that

      "In this theory, a system of N non-relativistic particles is described by a wave function which lives on configuration space, and by the actual positions of the particles. The positions evolve according to a 'guiding equation' which depends on the wave function, while the wave function itself obeys the Schro ̈dinger equation."

      This, along with the quantum equilibrium hypothesis, completely defines the theory. Of course the Hamiltonian must be prescribed by hand, and yes there one relies on experience from classical physics, but that then is true as much for standard QM and dynamic collapse as for BM. With the above structure, BM reproduces all the results of standard QM. And it does better, because the collapse of the wave-function / the projection postulate are not put in by hand in an ad hoc manners as a recipe to explain outcomes of experiments.

      We agree that one can easily write down the one particle / non-interacting relativistic BQM. But that is trivial isn't it? We always had the interacting relativistic QFT in mind.

      If by standard QM you mean the one with Copenhagen interpretation, we believe it is an incomplete theory. It does not explain what happens during a measurement - it merely postulates collapse of the wave-function without prescribing a mechanism for the collapse. We believe the least one would have to do to complete the theory is to adopt the many-worlds interpretation or BQM. Personally, we have difficulties with many worlds since we do not see how probabilities and the Born rule can come about in MW. So we would prefer BQM over MW.

      Alternatvely, collapse of the wave-function might be explained dynamically - we think this issue will be settled by experiments, because dynamic collapse theories make different predictions from BQM / standard QM in the yet untested mesoscopic domain.

      With our best regards,

      Authors

      Angelo, Saikat, & Tejinder,

      The information as embodied in particle properties (which can be thought of as internalized rules of behavior, the expression of laws of physics) in a self-creating universe must be the product of a trial-and-error evolution. If fundamental particles have to create themselves, each other and particles only exist to each other if and for as long as they interact, then particles, particle properties, 'its' must be as much the source as the product of their interactions, both cause and effect of a continuous energy / information exchange, then information only can evolve, become information when molded into material particles and tested in actual particle interactions: only such information survives which enables its embodiments to survive, to manifest themselves as real particles. So I don't see how you can have one without (before?) the other, how one can be more fundamental than the other.

      Regards, Anton

        Bohm QM is basically the Schrodinger equation split into a real and imaginary part. There is the Hamilton-Jacobi equation for the real part that includes this quantum potential term

        -∂S/∂t = H - (ħ^2/2m)∇^2R/R

        for the wave function ψ = Re^{-iS/ħ}. That quantum potential is associated with the guidance equation. There is an imaginary part which is formally a continuity equation. None of this is wrong exactly, but I think it is weak. The one problem is that it depends upon classical variables, where we know there are quantum observables that have no classical analogue. In addition quantum mechanics with its complementarity of observables permits one to work exclusively in the position or momentum representation. This is a halving of the number of degrees of freedom a theory needs. Bohm QM brings back the full phase space with {p, q} variables.

        I think this is potentially useful for quantum chaos, for the classical-like structure of this theory is I think better adapted to the techniques in classical perturbation theory and looking at KAM theorem results on puncturing invariant tori. The classical-like particle, called the beable, then traces out chaotic motion. Of course to my way of thinking this beable is really just a mathematical fiction of sorts. It is a gadget used to compute scarring in quantum chaos.

        The BQM is a sort of interpretation. It is meant to get around the cut-off problem with Copenhagen interpretation. MWI has been worked out with Born theorem. I think the big open question is contextuality. An observer is free to orient their Stern-Gerlach apparatus by choice. This selects the eigenbasis of a measurement, but the Kochen-Specker theorem tells us that QM has no such contextuality; QM treats all bases equivalently up to a unitary transformation. So this eigen-splitting of the world in MWI, where different observers record different results, has some sort of implicit contextuality.

        It is my general observation that QM interpretations that are meant to give some dynamics to a measurement, such as Bohm's QM does by tying things closely to classical physics, runs into their own set of difficulties. Quantum interpretations in my opinion are devices that can be employed for different problems, where some interpretation turns out to be more applicable. Now there is the rise of Qubism, which ties QM to Bayes' theorem, but as near as I can tell this ends up being just another interpretation.

        Cheers LC

        Dear Angelo, Saikat and Tejinder,

        I enjoyed reading the overview of the three alternatives to orthodox quantum mechanics. I did not previously know much about trace dynamics, so it was good to find out a bit more about it. It would have been nice if the experimental tests hinted at in the article would have been described a little, possibly including an expected date (if known) for when they are expected to be performed. Also, one might ask if it is possible to motivate the theories a little more. Obviously nature does not need to heed our prejudices, but it would be nice if she could be understood at the most fundamental level in a way that makes sense.

        I wish you all the best,

        Armin

          Dear Anton,

          We are not sure we understand your remarks. Perhaps you refer to a very broad context as to how information relates to matter, interactions and space-time. We have addressed only one aspect of that very broad issue: how the interpretation / understanding of probabilities in quantum theory can dictate the primacy of it over bit or vice versa.

          Best regards,

          Authors

          Dear Armin,

          Thank you for reading our essay and for your comments.

          The experiments have been going on since the nineties, and have put useful bounds on the theories. If you like you could see our recent review article in

          Reviews of Modern Physics 85 (2013) 471

          also available at

          http://arXiv.org/abs/arXiv:1204.4325

          where we discuss these experiments in detail, as also the motivations for the theories.

          Best regards,

          Authors

          Dear Dr. Singh,

          Your argument for an underlying deterministic basis for quantum theory is novel and very well presented!

          Using a Bohmian approach necessitates that there is an underlying quantum wholeness in which absolute probabilities are defined for every possible outcome. One way to approach this is by using quantum information theory.

          The emergence of classical spacetime from coarse graining classical matrix dynamics thus depends upon the conditional entropy of the observer. The measurement process arises out of her ignorance that this is just another aspect of dynamic evolution. Essentially, she erases the entanglement information of the underlying quantum wholeness. (See my essay "A Complex Conjugate It and Bit".)

          In this way, paralleling your theory, the "it" arises from the "bit".

          Best wishes,

          Richard

            Hi Angelo, Saikat, & Tejinder,

            Yes, my critique (and essay) is about what makes information into information as an answer to this question may give a clue as to whether nature at quantum level is random or not. I wonder if the following reasoning might make sense, and I would very much appreciate your answer.

            In classical mechanics (in general relativity and big bang cosmology) particles only are the cause of forces, so here one has to assume the existence of virtual photons and gravitons to transmit forces between real particles. Though the emission and absorption of virtual photons and gravitons to communicate forces between real particles is supposed to be random so their energy fluctuates randomly, they nevertheless obey the Uncertainty Principle [UP] according to which a deviation in the energy of a particle may last shorter as the deviation is greater. This of course begs the question how its neighbors can know when to supply the particle in a timely fashion with energy so it can obey the UP. If in this, classical view, the communication between particles is random, then particles only exist to each other, physically, at the random times they absorb a virtual particle from each other, so they only are intermittently part of each other's interaction horizon, each other's universe. In contrast, if in a Self-Creating Universe [SCU] particles have to create themselves, each other, if they only exist to each other if and for as long as they interact, then to keep existing, they must keep interacting continuously. If in a SCU particles, particle properties ultimately must be as much the source (cause) as the product (effect) of their interactions, of forces between them, then real particles can be thought of as virtual particles which by alternately borrowing and lending each other the energy to exist, force each other to reappear again and again after every disappearance, so they create and un-create each other over and over again without violating any conservation law. As in this scenario the energy sign of a particle alternates, it is a wave phenomenon: the higher the frequency its energy sign alternates (its sign flipping every time an increase turns into a decrease and vice versa), the higher its energy is. Instead of saying that its energy fluctuates randomly, in a SCU a particle exchanges all its energy in every cycle so the UP is just another formulation of the Planck relation E = h v, with v the frequency the a particle oscillates, exchanges energy at.

            It is the continuous energy exchange between particles by means of which they express and preserve each other's properties: preserving the status quo, this continuous exchange of energy aka information is too inconspicuous to be aware of, to assume its existence let alone identify it as the long sought-for 'hidden variables'. According to the UP, the shorter the distance is between particles, the higher the frequency they exchange energy at, the higher their rest energy is. So if the energy of a particle is the superposition of all frequencies it exchanges energy at with all particles within its interaction horizon, a frequency which depends on their mass, distance and motion, then a particle in its 'own' properties contains all relevant information about its entire universe, information which is refreshed in every cycle of its oscillation. Since E = h v states that energy is a quantity which is greater as its rate of change is greater and this rate, the energy of a particle varies within every cycle of its oscillation, then so does the (in)definiteness in both its position and momentum, that is, when we define the mass of a particle to be greater as its position is less indefinite (if the link doesn't work, see: www.quantumgravtity.nl, the chapter 'A definition of mass').

            In this, fully quantum mechanical view, we therefore cannot predict the outcome of particle interactions because we cannot know in what phase the particles are in when they collide or interact, so the probability of quantum theory does not originate in randomness. Randomness only would appear if particle properties would be constant, intrinsic i.e., privately owned, interaction-independent quantities: if they only would be the cause of forces, interactions but not also their product. The present confusion comes from trying to understand quantum mechanics (things like the double-slit experiment) while clinging to outdated, classical notions, in particular the idea of causality: the idea that mass can causally precede gravity, which of course is nonsense.

            Regards, Anton

            Hi Angelo, Saikat, & Tejinder,

            Yes, my critique (and essay) is about what makes information into information as an answer to this question may give a clue as to whether nature at quantum level is random or not. I wonder if the following reasoning might make sense, and I would very much appreciate your answer.

            In classical mechanics (in general relativity and big bang cosmology) particles only are the cause of forces, so here one has to assume the existence of virtual photons and gravitons to transmit forces between real particles. Though the emission and absorption of virtual photons and gravitons to communicate forces between real particles is supposed to be random so their energy fluctuates randomly, they nevertheless obey the Uncertainty Principle [UP] according to which a deviation in the energy of a particle may last shorter as the deviation is greater. This of course begs the question how its neighbors can know when to supply the particle in a timely fashion with energy so it can obey the UP. If in this, classical view, the communication between particles is random, then particles only exist to each other, physically, at the random times they absorb a virtual particle from each other, so they only are intermittently part of each other's interaction horizon, each other's universe. In contrast, if in a Self-Creating Universe [SCU] particles have to create themselves, each other, if they only exist to each other if and for as long as they interact, then to keep existing, they must keep interacting continuously. If in a SCU particles, particle properties ultimately must be as much the source (cause) as the product (effect) of their interactions, of forces between them, then real particles can be thought of as virtual particles which by alternately borrowing and lending each other the energy to exist, force each other to reappear again and again after every disappearance, so they create and un-create each other over and over again without violating any conservation law. As in this scenario the energy sign of a particle alternates, it is a wave phenomenon: the higher the frequency its energy sign alternates (its sign flipping every time an increase turns into a decrease and vice versa), the higher its energy is. Instead of saying that its energy fluctuates randomly, in a SCU a particle exchanges all its energy in every cycle so the UP is just another formulation of the Planck relation E = h v, with v the frequency the a particle oscillates, exchanges energy at.

            It is the continuous energy exchange between particles by means of which they express and preserve each other's properties: preserving the status quo, this continuous exchange of energy aka information is too inconspicuous to be aware of, to assume its existence let alone identify it as the long sought-for 'hidden variables'. According to the UP, the shorter the distance is between particles, the higher the frequency they exchange energy at, the higher their rest energy is. So if the energy of a particle is the superposition of all frequencies it exchanges energy at with all particles within its interaction horizon, a frequency which depends on their mass, distance and motion, then a particle in its 'own' properties contains all relevant information about its entire universe, information which is refreshed in every cycle of its oscillation. Since E = h v states that energy is a quantity which is greater as its rate of change is greater and this rate, the energy of a particle varies within every cycle of its oscillation, then so does the (in)definiteness in both its position and momentum, that is, when we define the mass of a particle to be greater as its position is less indefinite (see: www.quantumgravity.nl, the chapter 'A definition of mass').

            In this, fully quantum mechanical view, we therefore cannot predict the outcome of particle interactions because we cannot know in what phase the particles are in when they collide or interact, so the probability of quantum theory does not originate in randomness. Randomness only would appear if particle properties would be constant, intrinsic i.e., privately owned, interaction-independent quantities: if they only would be the cause of forces, interactions but not also their product. The present confusion comes from trying to understand quantum mechanics (things like the double-slit experiment) while clinging to outdated, classical notions, in particular the idea of causality: the idea that mass can causally precede gravity, which of course is nonsense.

            Regards, Anton

              Dear Tejinder,

              Thank you very much for replying to my post even if it is on my thread. Though I agree that ideas must be quantified in equations so they can be put to test, before quantifying things and risk wasting time on flawed ideas, I first have to make sure that they don't lead to contradictions, that they are philosophically, rationally sound and might possibly agree with observations, or, if not, whether observations can be interpreted differently so they do.

              If a new, good theory expands our understanding like being able to see the world for the first time in color instead of in black, gray and white, then present physics is still charting the world as it has shown itself in color by quantum and relativity theory. The fact that eighty years of efforts haven't solved the present contradictions nor led to an understanding why quantum mechanics works, strongly indicates that answers cannot be found within the current paradigm, formalisms. To solve some of those problems may require a new, different way of looking at things, of thinking about them, a view which may expose some key assumptions of the current paradigm to be invalid, as I argue in my essay and elaborate on in my post of 19 July.

              If and when (as argued in that post) particles, particle properties indeed are as much the cause as the effect of their interactions, of forces between them so a force cannot be either attractive or repulsive, always, of its own, so to say, then this opens up a new, not previously explored path to the unification of forces. As in classical mechanics particle properties are thought to be only the source, the cause of forces, here we need two opposite, independent forces to explain any equilibrium between particles. Such equilibrium not only would be very unstable (unless we can invent a mechanism to avoid this, like asymptotic freedom), as opposite forces must be powered by different, independent sources, i.e., by physically unrelated particle properties, they never can be unified even in principle. As far as I'm aware of, string theory starts from just that classical assumption (never mind the Higgs mechanism) so it will never succeed in what it is intended to do. String theory to me therefore is a prime example of what happens when we allow mathematic formalisms to head our investigations for lack of ideas. Based on a misunderstanding about the nature of mass, of gravity, string theory is only one of the current popular theories which, I think, cannot solve anything but instead are part of the problem.

              With regards, Anton

              Dear Dr. Tejinder Singh,

              I like your multifaceted approach and questioning of the concept of probability. One of my goals is to topple the uncertainty principle as a way to make physics "rational". I think I have made a good start with my essay. It would be wonderful to get your comments on my work, so please visit my blog.

              I am on my way to give your work a good mark.

              Thanks for the thoughtful essay,

              Don Limuti

                Tejinder et al,

                Nice! We are in full agreement that "it" is primary, i.e., IT may have an existence independent of BIT. Whether it *chooses* to do so, however, is the crux of the important question you ask:

                "When is an apparatus classical? Strictly speaking, we do not quite know." And we never have known at what point quantum phenomena are supposed to "smooth out" to become classical; quantum theory is simply incoherent if not infinitely extended. How, then, can it be both coherent and probabilistic?

                Reading the comments, we disagree that Bohmian mechanics is to be preferred over many worlds. A bifurcating multiverse is more satisfying to me because it preserves the topological simple connectedness that I conjecture is necessary to information conservation and classical time reversibility.

                No matter -- superb job, as always!

                Tom

                  Dear Angelo,

                  You write

                  "Here the it comes first [it being the particle / wave-function / matrix] and is well-defined even before the measurement is made."

                  This is where, according to quantum mechanics and the theory of measurements, I think, you are wrong. At least, now, I understand why your view contradicts the "it from bit" philosophy.

                  Best regards,

                  Michel

                  Dear Don,

                  Greetings and thanks for your kind comments. I very much hope to see your essay in the next few days.

                  Best,

                  Tejinder