Dear Derek,
Your essay reads very well and clear, so it invites many comments. In addition, I feel very close to many of your ideas.
1. You seem to depart from Wigner's definition of mathematics, and to avoid giving one, till you finally wonder how we can factor out the human element. What do you think of Grothendieck's testimony, in Récoltes et semailles? He describes mathematics as something which is to be explored, much like an unknown continent. Someone who does maths is in a relationship similar to his relationship to the world in general, though of course what we call mathematical objects are a special case of objects within the whole world. Wigner focuses on the final result, which Grothendieck criticises as missing the living ingredient, the active, the discovery, the history part. It is good that the mathematical discourse is eventually abstracted --and certainly Grothendieck does not refuse abstraction--, but if abstraction is presented at once, naked, it cannot be understood. Hence the stress is on abstraction, as something built by a subject. Poincaré has insisted on exactly the same points about teaching mathematics (La logique et l'intuition dans la science mathématique et l'enseignement, in L'Enseignement mathématique, 1899):
``By becoming rigorous, the mathematical science takes an artificial character that will strike everybody; it forgets its historical origins; one sees how to solve questions, not any more how, and why questions are posed at all.''
Do I follow you well, would you see that fit with the spirit of your essay?
2. You define reductionism as `ignoring'. I would point that discarding, or ignoring many aspects of a situation is a good definition of abstraction; in your own words: `stripping away all inessential details'. This aligns the two terms that you keep separate.
It is a very common observation that problems get simpler when they are seen in a more general frame: when they are (pertinently) abstracted.
Abstraction is not easy. The simplest example I can think of is the transition from numbers-of (something) to numbers (`pure'). Adherence to numbers-of is still clearly perceptible in the late 19tr century writings of Lazare Carnot, who violently dismissed negative numbers, because ``they where obtained by removing something from zero, an impossible operation'', and besides, ``-3 would be less than 2, and though (-3)^2 would be greater than 2^2, that is the square of the largest would be smaller than the square of the smallest, which shocks any clear idea of quantity''. (This opinion, in a given viewpoint, is perfectly fair: how can you take three sheep out of an empty field?). And here we see what is wrong in his view: he cannot forget that numbers used to represent quantities, so he enforces on them to carry on satisfying quantities constraints. At the same time, he sees clearly what the rules to operate on negative numbers are, to be coherent. Thus seen from today's commonplace thinking, most of us would wonder how he could both understand and not understand the issue of negative numbers. The answer is that abstraction is not easy. There are countless examples of such obstinate resistance to abstraction. There are rules you must abandon in some cases, to be able to extend the range of things you can represent. Also, we see that the full extension of the rules to manipulate numbers is not visible from the onset: it must be explored, with trial and error.
The underlying idea is very close to what Wigner captures in his definition: yes, the rules of composing numbers are like invented just for he purpose of being consistent, that's the point we reach when we abstract them more. They forget that we came to numbers by an
A formalised piece of mathematics does not exhaust the concepts. Neither in the mind of the mathematician, nor (even less), in a computing machine, for cases where an implementation is possible or makes sense. The implementation is bound to inputs and outputs in such a way that it cannot be applied to any sort of object without an adaptation.
3. So, here are my questions:
Do you imply that there is any other way to build a science, than reductionism, as you have defined it? (And its generalisation, I have pointed to.) I would like to read your vision about it.
4. To elaborate,
what I have called the basic hypothesis of physics is actually a reduction: that the observer can be considered completely separated from the world (and then, even more, totally elided). (You may refer to my essay, should you need to.) It is not obligatory to follow the usual interpretation that physics makes of this necessary reduction, though. I have outlined that you cannot do without a reference frame to describe any situation, and the ultimate reference frame is the individual. (And, being the observer who enunciates what we call science, there is nothing problematic in taking the existence of the living subject as granted, as an axiom.)
In addition, any law is necessarily expressed in terms of classes (if approximate). It is easily seen if we accept a space time-model of the universe (any{ sort of space-time): by construction, events are fixed entities in such a representation. Hence when we describe an experiment, and say is is reproducible, we sate that some set in space-time shows, from a given point of view (forgetting, abstracting all the `unnecessary'), identical to many other sets. Hence we describe classes in the huge sets of events. This means that any law intrinsically forgets many things that it deems unimportant, unnecessary... and thus is a reduction, in a sense that is perfectly consistent with your use.
If a situation is, in our theory, liable to the same law as another one, then it is in the name of a reduction. There is no sort of law that cannot be a reduction. We can even go even one step further: any perception proceeds by the building of categories, and from this abstract vantage point, perception and science appear in continuity (incidentally, this has been widely acknowledged in psychology --See e.g. Eleanor Rosch, or Lakoff, to whom Julian Barbour already referred to.) Or, said in other, less general words (those of mathematical analysis), perception is a smoothing of the world. For instance, when you see the cliff from a distance, you are warned in advance you are informed by a signal which is not as sharp as the cliff itself, it is exactly a smoothing of the cliff's curve.
Would you care to answer these questions, or react to these comments?