Terry
Thank you for your kind comments on my essay.
You mentioned: "reminiscent both of what Wheeler and Feynman did in their pre-QED advanced-retarded photon work". I have long had a copy, in book form, of Feynman's thesis so I am aware of advanced and retarded waves in time. You also mentioned on your essay website page that John Cramer's TIQM may be relevant in a similar way. I can now see that to be the case. However, I specifically have the electron travelling forward in time and the positron travelling backward in time whereas advanced and retarded waves may be more complicated than that. For example a photon travelling forward in time from A to B using minimum action has a transaction between A and B which implies B influences the photon even as it leaves A. My preon model was not used in my essay but it has an interesting property with respect to matter and antimatter that each individual standard model particle, for fermions and bosons, is composed of an equal number of matter and antimatter preons. And if positrons travel backwards in time then antimatter preons may do so too. This means that all particles are travelling in both time directions equally! This might make it more clear that even a single particle can, in my preon model, negotiate with both forwards and backwards-in-time influences in its own right. Which seems a positive point. However, preons are not the ones being acted upon direct by EM forces. And the observer standpoint always needs to be born in mind. The positron could be travelling backwards in time as a single entity while the preons inside it are travelling both ways in time. This could be similar to our universe having its own time direction, set by entropy increase, while still having antiparticles travelling backwards in time. Indeed, my idea of a time direction for an electron is actually a time direction within the electron, similar to the time direction of the universe in a particle-universe equivalence model. This would require electrons to have extended substance (ie preons)and to have internal processes ongoing such as entropy increase within the electron. This is similar for particles to the lifetimes of the universe in the Penrose CCC model. Measurement of an electron would involve catastrophic breakdown of its internal space metric (similar to that in CCC) and that process would not enable the electron position at point B to be calculable for an individual electron.
You wrote: "If you can travel both ways in time, speed of light constraints become meaningless, and you can almost trivially get correlations. " Well, yes, the speed of light constraints do trivially disappear. But, the correlations only arise because the incoming beam of electrons to Bob has been polarised.
I am glad that you liked the use of a 200 year old formula! I used Malus as I wanted to try to move away from all the Bell philosophical baggage. I have long had a hang up that complicated Bell experiments had issues with measurement loopholes. But I have no such hang up about Malus experiments. Yet I noticed that my simple simulations for Bell could not break the inequality (by getting correlation = 0.707 at 45 degrees for electrons). But neither could I get an intensity greater than 0.75 for Malus at 45 degrees for electrons, which is equivalent to the mundane classical correlation of 0.5. That led direct to the work comparing Bell with Malus. And then I realised that by time reversal for antiparticles I could get polarisation and hence QM results for Bell.
Thank you for suggesting an opening wording for my essay: ""In this essay I show that if you simply assume that Wheeler-Feynman style retrocausal interactions are an inherent component of Bell inequality dynamics, then unpredictability of the outcomes becomes an inherent and unavoidable consequence in all situations. This is true even if quasi-classical hidden variable models are assumed, and in fact this approach allows such models to meet Bell's inequality even while using hidden variables. Thus in this analysis, indeterminacy becomes a deep and unavoidable consequence of how quantum mechanics works in our universe."
I like the glossiness of this text but it does not sound like me, alas. I would only point to one ambiguity. The way I read this, it implies that unpredictability only arises from retrocausal interactions. IMO unpredictability can also be found without retrocausality. (However in my preon model I am not sure if an absence of retrocausality can exist anywhere.) I see unpredictability in the loss of wavefunction of a particle being exactly similar to the catastrophic loss of the space metric in the universe at the end of a CCC cycle. (Particle being equivalent to a universe.) By analogy if a soap bubble could retain unitary on catastrophic bursting, how could one calculate where that single final point would be? I do have a paper on this which can be found by a google search using my name and 'Rasch'. In the paper, I make metrics for various conditions of data. Some metrics embrace all the data, but some have catastrophic gaps where not all data are placed in the metric. The condition where the metric breaks down is where the data are widely separated from one another in space. This is exactly what occurs at the end of a cycle in CCC.